Jumping into the debate about “bleeding-heart libertarianism” (Matt Zwolinski and John Tomasi, Bryan Caplan and again, David Friedman, David Henderson, and others), which seeks to integrate libertarianism with social justice. “Social justice” is one of those vaguely-specified, usually suspect phrases, defined by one defender of BHL as the position that “the moral justification of our institutions depends on how well these institutions serve the interests of the poor and least advantaged.”
Thus stated, BHL accepts the basic Rawlsian line about the morality of politics, and its advocates seek either (a) to wrest the “social justice” label away from the lefties who use it most by showing that ends of social justice are best achieved by free-market liberalism, as Edmund Phelps tries to do, or (b) to find common ground with lefties on moral issues.
Five quick points against BHL:
1. As a political-philosophical method: BHL says we should start politics by dividing people into groups and granting one group special prior ethical status. In this case, BHL divides people into poor and non-poor and holds the poor to have a special moral position in politics-making. That is not the way to ground politics, for two reasons: (a) Politics should start with individuals, not individuals-as-members-of-a-sub-group; and (b) politics should initially treat all individuals as having equal moral status — in my view, as self-responsible, free agents — not as having preferred status by belonging to a sub-group.
2. As a moral justification of liberty: BHL says your liberty and mine are justified only if and to the extent that it serves or benefits the interests of others, especially poor others. This means that its moral principle is serving or benefiting others. This is not the way to do the ethics of politics: Liberty as a basic principle means that each individual’s life is his or her own, whether or not the individual’s choices serve or benefit others. Individuals’ political freedom is justified because they need it in order to think and act independently to produce the values their lives need. My liberty to be a philosopher or a poet or an explorer is not morally contingent upon my doing so’s demonstrably serving the interests of others.
It’s fine to argue the general point that free-market liberalism leads to win-win results for everyone involved, and it’s a worthy effort to show how free markets are beneficial to various sub-groups — women, immigrants, the poor, and so on — but all of that is a consequent sub-topic to the basic moral point that individuals have a right to live their own lives freely.
3. As a conception of life’s core values: By focusing on the poor, BHL seems to make politics essentially or primarily about economics. If political institutions are to be designed by reference to their relative economic impact on the poor and non-poor, then economic wealth is the critical factor. But that is much too narrow a conception of liberty’s scope and the proper purpose of politics. Family, art, sports, religion, and so on, as well as economic pursuits, are parts of life, and the principles of politics should cover them all generally. A narrow conception of BHL would seem to imply that one is free to engage in art, religion, or whatever only if that can be shown to be to serve the interests of the poor.
Or perhaps the BHLs intend for poor to be taken more metaphorically to refer to anyone in a weaker position in any sphere of human life. The final phrase in the above definition adds the “least advantaged.” But then BHL implies that the political rules governing family, religion, and so on, should be crafted to serve the interests of the least advantaged participants. For example, in basketball, short people are less likely to be successful. Does the BHL principle imply that the rules of basketball should be devised and justified by reference to their ability to improve the basketball outcomes of the short? Or religion: Who would the least-advantaged members of religious groups be, and what would it mean to craft political rules about religion to serve their interests? Not a perfect analogy, but: Politicians should not care about the poor any more than they do about men who can’t get a woman to start a family with them — or any more than referees care about short basketball players.
4. As a marketing strategy: This is only speculation, but I know a number of libertarians who complain that their position comes across as too rational and coldly analytic. So to gain broader appeal, they argue, libertarians need to go out of their way to show that they have feelings and care. So perhaps the BHL strategy is to lead with their emotions by emphasizing their empathy.
Well, certainly reason and passion should be integrated, and a morally normal person feels for those who are in poverty through no fault of their own. This takes us into the fascinating territory of the moral emotions, and for BHL our question should be: Why should exhibiting those particular feelings be primary in making the case for a free society? Other passions are part of the morally-healthy package: Admiration for those who have achieved a lot. Anger at those who violate rights. Respect for those who exhibit independence and integrity. And of course empathy for those who are struggling with poverty. But empathy for the poor is not more morally special than respect for integrity or anger at bullies and tyrants, and it is a mistake to single it out for special foundational political status. Instead, political theorists concerned with the moral foundations of liberal society should be concerned with general principles of moral character that enable individuals to live freely.
(Side note: I think a case can be made that admiration for achievement is a more important moral emotion than empathy for the poor is, but that is another post.)
5. As a rhetorical strategy to get the lefties who dominate academic life to talk to us: Again a speculation, but perhaps BHL is partly an internal-to-academics strategy to make nice with the social justice crowd in order to get a seat at the table. Maybe there is some merit to this strategy, and I am all for seeking common ground when possible. But our problem with “social justice” academics is not that they just didn’t realize that we care about the poor too. The modern history of the social-justice movement from Rousseau to Marx to the 20th century is not a story of people with an unworkable theory but whose hearts are in the right place. Of course, social-justice academics come in a variety of degrees, and it may be that some of the moderate and open-minded ones will listen to our case if they are first convinced that we genuinely care about the poor. Fine. But that is at most a tactic within the overall strategy of making the case for the free society, which requires hard-nosed economics, plenty of empirical history, and vigorous and passionately-argued ethics of individualism.
[Update: Further commentaries on BHL: Jason Kuznicki, Jacob Levy, Andrew Cohen, Will Wilkinson, Jason Brennan, John McCaskey.]
Your point about the arbitrary choice of ensuring equality in the realm of economic security echoes very nicely Anthony de Jasay’s arguments against equality in his book _The State_. Also, the Left often seems to conflate compassion for those less well off than the upper class with those who are truly suffering deprivation. It’s true that some on the Left call for world-wide redistribution of goods, but the “sensible” Left does not; they only want national socialism, that way the money for the bureaucrats stays here at home. The wretched poor in the Third World can wait. Speaking of National Socialism: I discovered your film Nietzsche and the Nazis on Netflix. I was riveted. I hope you produce more such films in the future.
Good points all, Stephen.
Yours is an excellent view of the broader issues and I have saved into my reference files. On the narrower point of BHL as Libertarianism, I offer:
The fundamental issues in Libertarianism are the functions of government and the effects of those functions on Liberty.
There is nothing wrong with saying that in addition to those effects on Liberty (of prime concern to Libertarians) there should be [equal?] concern with other effects. There is nothing wrong with BHL demonstrations of the effects of those functions on the poor (or any other segment) as a class.
Now, if BHL were limited to assertions that in addition to those effects on Liberty (of prime concern to Libertarians) there should be [equal?] concern with other effects, that would be a call for “opening of hearts.” But, to go further, and suggest that “concern for the poor” or correcting perceived maladjustments of the distributive system should be an objective of the functions of government for libertarians, is not fissaporous (another fragmented version); it is a different political concept; opposing to, and destructive of Libertarian objectives.
On behalf of BHL, in side stepping the “Social Justice” positions, it has been asserted: “. . . that consequentialism provides both a clear and defensible normative approach that explains why the poor should receive our special consideration – to an extent.”
Do those convictions relate to the “normative” issues of Libertarianism; or, are they no more than an articulation of a philosophical justification of what “should” be (‘to an extent”) one of the conditions of human relations to be sought – implying [?] to be sought though our modes of governance (the functions and operative effects of governments)?
Consequentialism is a philosophical “argument.” Because it concerns judgments of actions on the basis of moral objectives to be sought, attempts to apply that philosophy to the determination of the functions and operative effects of governments is distinct from normative Libertarianism.
One might say that philosophical issue and Libertarianism are each concerned with “consequences” of the determinations of the functions and operative effects of governments; a consequentialists for what “ought” to be the consequences (and particularly how they are to be judged); and a libertarian for consequences to be avoided (to the extent possible).
The determinations sought by consequentialists would appear to require creating constructs for governance; that is, creating governmental functions and operative effects for specific moral objectives.
Normative Libertarianism does not encompass that course for attaining moral objectives. Further, the empirical evidence is not yet available to support a consequentialist “approach” to the functions of governments.
The BHL so far disclosed is not Libertarian.
Good article.
The issue I have with BHL is their observed (my observation, and I’m willing to entertain evidence to the contrary) propensity to carve out exceptions that permit them to coerce their preferred outcomes. Their consequentialism appears to boil down to “the end justifies the means.”
BHL. Really? Sounds like liberaltarianism redux, which was a colossal flop because it deserved to be. They might be nice guys, but Cato was right to dismiss Brink Lindsey and Will Wilkenson.
The addled notion of “social justice” has no place in libertarian thought. Yours is a good refutation, but here’s the shorter version: “Libertarian” and “social justice” are mutually contradictory.
At best, “libertarian social justice” is an oxymoron. Hayek was even more critical of the notion of “social justice” in “The Mirage of Social Justice”:
“[The term] ‘social justice’ does not belong to the category of error but to that of nonsense, like the term ‘a moral stone.’”
BHL. Nonsense indeed.
That’s not to say, however, that a libertarian can’t have a bleeding heart. He can also have his own religious faith or none at all, smoke pot or jog every day, eat meat three meals a day or be a strict vegan, etc., etc. That’s his own business, and quite distinct from the libertarian ethics. Still, he can advocate that fellow libertarians become more compassionate and generous. But to argue that compassion and generosity are required by or are somehow inherent to libertarian ethics? No way. He may as well argue that all libertarians must smoke pot because the drug war violates libertarian ethics. It’s that absurd.
Of course, the libertarian concept of justice is entirely different from the communitarian or collectivist concept of justice. The libertarian has concrete criteria for determining whether a human act is just or unjust. Did the actor coerce or defraud another person? Did his action aggress upon another person or trespass upon his property? If not, the actor’s action is just. The libertarian rules for just conduct are easy to understand. The communitarian or collectivist concept of social justice is entirely different. It provides the individual no rules of just conduct. It merely serves as a means to criticize a free society for failing to achieve utopia and to urge an addled altruism to atone for collective guilt.
Oops. I failed to mention the main purpose of the collectivist concept of social justice: to deceive people into accepting the legitimacy of coercion, fraud, aggression, and trespass by the State to achieve the ends of the ruling elite.
WRT point #5. It is really naive to think that academic lefties will respond favorably to BHL or much care about libertarianism at all.
“Mr. Roark, we’re alone here. Why don’t you tell me what you think of me? In any words you wish. No one will hear us.”
“But I don’t think of you.”
Roark is a pretty good role model in this regard.
So it is basically collectivist libertarianism which states that the content of one’s mind is unequivocally directly proportional to poverty.The same kind of thinking also lead to racism, with only skin color instead of poverty.
They just don’t get it. You can’t counter fire with fire, likewise you can’t counter discrimination with discrimination.
Alexis De Tocqueville, writing of early 19th century America, marveled at its social cohesiveness, noting that the misfortune of one was felt by the entire community and all rallied to help. Today compassion is largely seen as the government’s job.
Much of the impetus to America’s welfare state came from New England’s socialist elites. In the prelude leading up to Johnson’s War on Poverty it must be asked: why the hugely weighted focus on the lifeboat ethics of the failure of blacks and other poor? Why not a focus on empowering them instead? On bringing them to equality and joining in the general prosperity? Was it really equality they wanted for them? Fortunately the silent majority of blacks and other disenfranchised poor avoided the welfare trap and quietly struggled to build decent and productive lives for themselves.
While many on the left, including the Marxist scholars who dominate Western political science departments, will argue that Bolshevism, Maoism, et al were perversions of Marx’s thought, few will brand his system itself psychopathic, though the direct murder of a hundred million people and the enslavement of a quarter of mankind was perpetrated in its name under his imposing hirsute visage.
Socialists and Marxists plead that this is unfair: that their ideals were noble but perverted in implementation. But it has been suggested that if every attempt to practice a noble ideal consistently results in tyranny, economic ruin and genocidal carnage perhaps the time has come to stop blaming human nature and instead call into question the nature of the ideal – and ask what makes it so noble. Advocates of capitalism also argue that their ideals were perverted in implementation by statist intrusions. Yet even in its very incomplete and imperfect incarnation it has brought mankind the greatest liberty, prosperity, opportunity, power and general well-being it has known.
One doesn’t typically hear the charge the Jefferson perverted Locke’s ideals.